Bij
het maken van het vorige blog over Michiel Wielema, ontdekte ik dat vorig jaar
dit boek is uitgekomen;
Anna
Tomaszewska & Hasse Hämäläinen (Eds.), The
Sources of Secularism: Enlightenment and Beyond. Palgrave
Macmillan, 2017 - 323 pagina's
Daarvoor
leverde Henri Krop een bijdrage, n.l.
Henri
Krop, Chapter 5 “The Secularism of Spinoza and His Circle," p. 71 – 99 – books.google
Hierna
neem ik (zonder de verwijzingen) de inleiding en de conclusie van het artikel
over. Het geeft een duidelijk verschil van benadering aan van Henri Krop en Wiep
van Bunge enerzijds en Jonathan Israel anderzijds op de betekenis van Spinoza
en zijn kring voor de secularisatie.
INTRODUCTION:
"SECULARISM" AND HEGEL'S "PROTESTANT PRINCIPLE"
In
the preface to the Philosophie des Rechts
(1820), Hegel coined the phrase "das Prinzip des Protestantismus."
This principle addresses human autonomy and freedom. Philosophy made this
religious principle "real" and Enlightenment philosophers and French
revolutionaries accomplished the work Luther began. By removing the obstacles between
God and man, Protestantism had abolished the medieval separation between clergy
and laity. Man regained the true consciousness of God's infinite love, and this
love transforms society as a whole. Luther's reformation implied a revolution
of human life. The medieval Church subverted human morality by promoting the
belief in an afterlife and imposing continence, celibacy, and poverty, which
undermine the virtues of civil society. Roman Catholicism preserved "this
separation of the religious from the secular." According to Hegel,
Luther's revolt implied the "secularity" (Weltlichkeit) of Christianity by integrating religion into the
world and making it part of our life. Hegel's concept of secularisation implied
a rationalisation of religion and an immanent morality. In this paper, I would
like to argue in favour of the thesis that Spinoza's philosophical project
implied secularisation in Hegel's sense. This position, I will establish by
outlining not only Spinoza's views, but also the highly controversial ideas of
Jarig Jelles (1620-1683), Adriaan Koerbagh (1632-1669) and Lodewijk Meyer
(1629-1681).
Jonathan
Israel links Spinoza with secularism but in another sense. He observes:
"Radical Enlightenment has been the 'general rationalisation and
secularisation' of Europe, which set in after 1650." By challenging
Christianity, radical philosophy decisively contributed to creating
"modernity." This "radical philosophy" emanated from
Spinoza and his allics. Unlike Hegel, Israel suggests that "radical
philosophy" culminated in atheism and materialism. However, as Wiep Van
Bunge argued, Spinoza and his friends focused on God. They asked for the
purification of Christianity from superstition, such as belief in miracles and
mysteries, rather than its abolishment. Spinoza's circle wanted the Church to
become integrated into society and all privileges of the clergy to be
eliminated. These ideals of rationalisation and equality fit well within the
program of the Radical Reformation.
The
"secularisation" envisaged by Spinoza's circle is inextricably linked
with a political project. In the preface to the recent edition of Koerbagh's A light, van Bunge draws attention to
the fact that the members of the circle supported the civil power agenda of the
so-called States Party. Spinoza's Tractatus
Theologico-Politicus (henceforth TTP) may well be read as a piece of
propaganda upholding the view of the States Party. In the preface, Spinoza
maintains that the state he lives in is an ideal state. However, the clergy,
driven by their lust for power, threatens the peaceful existence of the Republic.
According to the German historian Schilling, the anticlericalism of the States
Party originated in the party strife during the so-called Regime of True
Freedom, but its "Republicanism" did not exclude a general Christian
outlook and a Biblical underpinning. The secularism these radical philosophers argued
for was an attempt to solve the divisive problems challenging social unity in
the Dutch Republic.
In
this paper, I will examine the concept of "rational religion"
developed by Spinoza and his circle and its implications on the Bible (Section
"On Religion and the Bible"). Naturalistic morality originating in
human desires or affects and an exclusive concern with this world will then
follow (Section "Secular Morality in Koerbagh, Jelles, and Spinoza").
And, finally, I examine the complete subjection of the church to the authority
of the state, which is supposed to lead to the creation of "a Heaven on
Earth" (Section "The Abolition of the Ecclesiastical Power").
Before dealing with these topics, the next section will focus on "the
circle of Spinoza." Spinoza's philosophical project may be studied as part
of the movement.
Conclusion
Although
the TTP does not convey that Spinoza shared Koerbagh's and Meyer's optimism
with respect to the emancipatory powers of reason, Spinoza's circle shared a
common view on religion, which firstly implied that true religion could be
based on reason alone, simple and purified of all mystery and of the Roman-Catholic
superstition. A naturalistic morality coincides with such a rational religion.
Secondly, Spinoza's circle was influenced by Socinianism and, thirdly, it
pleaded an ardent anti-clericalism, convinced of the moral perversion of a
church striving for political power. I hope to have substantiated the claim
that the texts of Jelles, Koerbagh, Meyer and Spinoza, mostly written during
the five years between 1665 and 1670, should be read as political interventions
in the public debate during the "Era of True Freedom," the first period
in which the Dutch Republic had no stadtholder. However, they are also a part
of the history of secularisation, a process in which, from the Reformation
onwards, religion has been gradually deprived of its "sacred" nature
and integrated into the world. In this manner, religion has been incorporated
into our moral life.
Geen opmerkingen:
Een reactie posten