Over dit onderwerp kom je geen literatuur tegen. Een boek als
dat van Erik de Bom (red.), Een nieuwe
wereld. Denkers uit de Nederlanden over politiek en maatschappij (1500-1700)
[Uitgeverij Polis / Klement, ] heeft aparte hoofdstukken over Desiderius
Erasmus, Juan Luis Vives, Justus Lipsius, Leonardus Lessius, Hugo Grotius en
Benedictus de Spinoza. Maar wat Spinoza eventueel met Erasmus had, komt in z’n
boek niet aan de orde. De Duitse Spinoza Bibliografie geeft op één uitzondering na, niets met beide namen samen. De enige titel die de namen van beide denkers in zich
heeft, is het boek van Richard H. Popkin’s The
History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza [Berkeley [e.a.]: Univ. of
California Press., 1979. - XXII, 333 pp. – books.google],
maar voor zover ik mij herinner van bestudering enige jaren terug geeft ook
Popkin daarin niets over Spinoza’s kijk op Erasmus. Verrassenderwijs bracht
google mij onder ogen het boek van
Lewis Samuel Feuer, Spinoza and the Rise of Liberalism [Transaction Publishers, 1987 – books.google] dat op p. 72 deze passage heeft waarin de
namen van beiden voorkomt (ik laat ze oplichten)
Dit is tegelijk een mooie inleiding op wat ik in dit
blog verder breng.
Eénmaal slechts verwijst Spinoza naar Erasmus, namelijk in de Tweede Zamenspreekinge in de Korte Verhandeling – waar Feuer al naar verwees. Daarin laat Spinoza Erasmus optreden in een gesprek met Theophilus. Theophilus heeft de rol waarin Spinoza’s leer nader wordt toegelicht; zoals de ondertitel ook aangeeft is de opzet van de dialoog “Dienende eensdeels tot dat voorgaande, anderdeels tot het twede Navolgende Deel”. In een volgend blog – zo ben ik van plan -zal ik deze dialoog tussen Erasmus en Theophilus brengen.
Hier haal ik graag een deel naar binnen van het hoofdstuk van Russ Leo, “Spinoza’s Calvin: Reformed Theologiy in the Korte Verhandeling van God, de Mensch en Deszelfs Welstand,: in Yitzhak Y. Melamed, The Young Spinoza. Oxford University Press, 2015, p. 144-159 – books.google. Het is de enige tekst die ik kon vinden, waarin iets dieper wordt ingegaan op Spinoza’s visie op Erasmus – we krijgen er ook iets méér analyse dan bij Feuer.
Russ
Leo geeft daar een overtuigende toelichting op wat Spinoza daar voorhad met het
opvoeren van Erasmus. Hij laat zien dat Spinoza met zijn zorgvuldige
behandeling in de Korte Verhandeling
van het thema ‘voorzienigheid en predestinatie’ de opzet had een kring van
‘calvinisten’ te bereiken die vertrouwd was met de scholastieke achtergrond van
de gereformeerde theologie en de groeiende hoeveelheid spirituele literatuur
die in de Nederlanden gepubliceerd werd. Leo ziet dan ook Spinoza met zijn KV zich bevinden tussen de 17e
eeuwse gereformeerde theologie enerzijds en de eenvoudige vroomheid van de Nadere
Reformatie anderzijds. En hij vervolgt dan aldus [ ik
geef wel het verwijzingsgetal, maar voor de noten verwijs ik naar het boek]:
Spinoza
knew his audience well. Lest we forget, it is his explicit invocation of
Erasmus in the dialogue [Zamenspreekinge]
between Erasmus and Theophilus (KV 76-79, before 1 3) that frames the chapters
of the KV on causality, God's necessary activity, providence, and
predestination. Spinoza's Erasmus denies that God can act simultaneously as an
immanent cause, a remote cause, and an internal cause; Theophilus, correcting
Erasmus gently, proceeds to explain how this is in fact possible. Here Spinoza
subtly recalls Erasmus's most famous disputation, his 1524 De libero arbitrio diatribe sive collatio against Martin Luther,
his affirmation of free will and foreknowledge against Luther's versions of
justification and predestination, translating their humanist disagreement into
distinctly scholastic terms. Spinoza's Second Dialogue works as a sort of
fable, through which readers proceed toward his more detailed treatments of
causality, agency, and predestination in God. He guides his readers through
Erasmus to the Reformed scholasticism of the KV, appealing to a variety of
contemporaries between Amsterdam, Rijnsburg, and Rotterdam during the 1650s and
early 1660s for whom Erasmus and his legacy were crucial to Dutch politics,
philosophy, and religion. Such people were among Spinoza's chief
interlocutors—for instance, Jacob Ostens (1630-1678) of the Rotterdam
"Waterlanders," or Meyer, author of the Philosophia S. Scripturae interpres (1666).36 The
controversial Rotterdammer Joachim Oudaan (1628-1692) is also a signal figure
here. Considering his public profile, it is difficult to believe that Spinoza
had not heard of Oudaan.37 During the 1650s and 1660s, Oudaan was
singularly preoccupied with that most famous citizen of his native Rotterdam,
Erasmus. Since 1622, when Remonstrant politicians established control over [156] Rotterdam,
Hendrik de Keyser's copper statue of Erasmus stood prominently in the city
center.38 Earlier in the seventeenth century, after the exclusion of
the Remonstrants following the Synod of Dort. Erasmus could number among his followers
the renowned poet, scholar, and jurist Hugo Grotius (1583-1645); Caspar
Barlaeus (1584-1648). the first professor of philosophy and rhetoric at the
Amsterdam Athaneum Illustre (the
institution founded in 1631 that would eventually become the Universiteit van
Amsterdam); and the influential Remonstrant preachers Johannes Uytenbogaert
(1557-1644) and Simon Episcopius (1583-1643)—all of whom were crucial
authorities in the intellectual world of the Remonstrants and Collegiants. It
is during this period that the citizens of Rotterdam erected de Keyser's statue
of Erasmus, perhaps as a form of resistance against the Counter-Remonstrant
consensus, perhaps as a measure of solidarity among the dissenters who survived
the purges and expulsions. We are told that Grotius visited the monument once
he returned to the United Provinces from exile in 1631. He is reported as
saying, "My first visit to Rotterdam was to show my affection for the
memory of Erasmus. I went to see the statue of the man who had so well shown us
the way to a measured Reformation. never binding himself on disputable
questions to one side or another. We Hollanders cannot thank this man enough,
and I hold myself fortunate that I can from afar understand his virtue."39
The statue was removed in 1674. when Countra-Remonstrants and Orangists seized
control of the city following the events of the 1672 rampjaar, but it was erected again in 1677—this time upon a new
pedestal featuring text by Nikolaes Heinsius and Oudaan.40 This was,
in many ways. an exemplary gesture commemorating over a century of Dutch
interest in Erasmus, championing his alleged irenicism, humanism, spiritualism,
and simplicity against what contemporaries felt was the reigning climate of
Reformed severity, dogmatism, and intolerance. Among Spinoza and his
contemporaries, many of the poets, philosophers. and theologians who were drawn
to the Collegiant movement were duly devoted to Erasmus and the spiritual
Reformation that never quite happened in the Netherlands. Even among Remonstrants
(such as Grotius and, later, Oudaan), for whom a certain version of Reformed
theology still held sway, Erasmus was an important authority against the
Contra-Remonstrant Calvinism of their opponents. Spinoza. moving from a
deliberate admonishment of Erasmus to a distinctly Reformed approach to
providence and predestination, engages these readers. as well as those
Calvinists for whom Erasmus was just another medieval Catholic to overcome.
Whereas
the engagement with Erasmus is brief and strategic, however, Calvin and
Calvinism are more than rhetorical turns in the KV. Indeed, upon closer look,
Spinoza uses Reformed concepts to structure the distinction between belief and
knowledge. In II 4, Spinoza establishes that "true belief is thus only
good insofar as it is the way to true knowledge, awakening us to those things
that are truly worth loving."41 This comes after he
demonstrates the differences between opinion [waan], belief [geloof],
and knowledge [weeten] and, of
course, also after his more detailed scholastic expositions of necessary
activity, providence, predestination, and causality in God in Part I. The
treatment of true belief in Part II rests on the exposition of these concepts
in Part I; moreover, consider the strange foundation for human understanding in
I 9 on "Natured Nature" [genatuurde
Natuur], which Spinoza will later refer to in a Latin register as Natura Naturata, where Spinoza names
"the understanding in the thinking thing" [het verstaan in de denkende zaak] as "a Son, Product, or
immediate Creation of God" [een
Zone, Maaksel, or unmiddel9k schepzel van God] (KV 287-288). It is
difficult to miss or ignore the Trinitarian suggestion here, however vague and
however disconnected ' from the initial invocation of "the Lord Christ our
best teacher" [Heer Christus, onzen
besten Leermeester] on the title page (KV 245). Thus it is the
understanding in the thinking thing—a "Son" of God, a type of thing
that "[has] been for all eternity and will remain unchanging for all
eternity" [van alle eeuwigheid zyn geweest, en in alle eeuwigheid
onveranderlÿk zullen blÿven]—that men attain either through true belief or
clear knowledge [klare kennis],
neither of which can err (KV 288, 298). Spinoza, however subtly, allows his
more pious readers to locate not just a
but the Son as a conceptual mediator
between "Natured Nature" [genatuurde
Natuur] and "Naturing Nature" [Naturende Natuur]; between knowledge of God in se and for man; and between nature, providence, and
predestination, when apprehended either through true belief or true knowledge.
At the heart of the KV we encounter a rational Christology buttressed by
Reformed approaches to providence and predestination and the knowledges
thereof.
Thanks for informative Posting. I agree with the point that Spinoza is discussing Erasmus with a Calvinist audience in mind. However, I have a hard time agreeing that Spinoza's intention is to present a "rational Christology" that a Calvinist could support. This is because Spinoza's Christology is incompatible with traditional Calvinist doctrine as determined by the Council of Dort, so I think Ruth Leo's argument needs to be clarified a bit more.
BeantwoordenVerwijderen